Philosophy of Science
**WARNING: The
following review of materials for a course in the philosophy of science is
necessarily long and exhaustive, replete with the confusing jargon of both the
fields of philosophy and science, as well as the unique jargon that emerges
when the concepts of each field of study is unleashed upon the other. It will
require patience and time to wade through these waters, but for those
interested in this essential inquiry, the reward will be well worth the
effort—S.I.P. Blogger.
“Getting the Course”
[Just skip the first 3 paragraphs if you only want to see material review.]
Around this time last year, my brother was looking for some
intellectually challenging audio material to listen to during his daily
commute, which is an hour and a half one-way. We’ve both been frequent
listeners to audio books of non-fiction and literature; however, our true
commute-driven audio passion has been for university lectures, particularly
those produced by The Teaching Company
under the titular series The Great
Courses. I have reviewed other courses in this series frequently on this
blog. Ironically, I discovered The Teaching Company and their excellent
lectures in my last semester prior to graduating with my Bachelor of Arts
degree.
Of course, I quickly introduced the lectures to my brother
and we have been loyal customers ever since. At the time, The Teaching Company
was the only source of recorded lectures readily available. These days, there
are numerous sources of such lectures: The
Modern Scholar, iTunes U, podcasts,
and individual university offerings such
as MIT’s Open Courseware—just to
name a few. I mention all of this only to explain to you that neither of us is
an amateur when it comes to consumption of recorded academic lectures and
coursework. So, when my brother was looking for something challenging last
year, we did some research and comparison and finally settled on The Great
Courses’ Philosophy
of Science. The outline indicated that the course addressed topics we
had both encountered but not understood or studied in previous settings: logical
positivism, the problem of demarcation, Karl Popper, axioms, a theory of
everything, etc.
After getting the CDs, I waited about a week and then asked
him how the course was going. Now, not to bloat his ego, but we’re talking
about someone who has an IQ in the 160 range and a nearly eidetic memory. “It’s
rough, man,” he responded. “I hate to say it, but I’m just going to have to
quit it. It’s just too abstract and complex—I find it hard to follow.” So, he
did quit it. The first time either of us had shied away from a course. I was
thoroughly intimidated. The course just sat around for the next year. Then,
finally, about a month ago, I decided it was time to slay this beast. “Good
luck, man,” said my brother, when I told him of my intention.
“Experiencing the
Course”
On 8/3/2014 I completed The Great Courses series on Philosophy of Science which was
presented by Professor Jeffrey L. Kasser, PhD. He is an Assistant Professor of
Philosophy at Colorado
State University.
His undergraduate degree is from Rice University and his doctoral study was completed at
the University of
Michigan. My completion
where my brother failed was, however, a far cry from a celebratory occasion.
Understanding the philosophy of science requires one to move in a circular
(perhaps elliptical?) orbit around the same pertinent questions that have
plagued the study from at lwawt
At first, the 18 hours might sound slim for a full course on
the philosophy of science. I can assure you it is not.
With the production style of The Teaching Company, ideas
come quickly and elaboration even quicker. These lectures are planned and
efficient. If you went to a university where the standard sixteen week course was
3 classes of 50 minute lectures per week, with alternating Fridays, then you
remember very easily that this does not translate into the following
relationship: (50 min x 3 days) + (50 min x 2 days) / 2 = a mean average of 125
minutes per week x 16 wks = 2000 min / 60 min/hr = 33.3 hours of instruction.
That is quite a fantasy. I attended three state schools and five private
colleges during my extended academic career and always found the same thing: At
least the first 10 minutes were concerned with review of the previous lecture
material. Another 15 minutes were typically used for answering student
questions throughout the lecture or at the end of the course as well as various
administrative matters (announcements, anecdotes, etc.) Finally, there were
almost always two entire class sessions devoted to review of the midterm and
final exams and two for the actual conduct of those exams.
All of this means that the typical classroom student loses (let’s
be conservative) around 20 minutes of lecture/instruction time for each
class—bringing the actual time down to 30 minutes per class session. Then, we
must account for the total of 4 completely lost classes concerned with
examinations (100 + 100 = 200). Thus, we arrive at the following calculation of
actual time devoted to lecture/instruction in a typical 3 semester hour credit
course: (30 min x 3 days + 30 min x 2 days)/2 wks = a mean average of 75
minutes per week x 16 wks = 1200 min – 200 min (the 4 days devoted to exams) =
1000 min / 60 min/hr = 16.7 or approximately 17 hours of lecture/instruction
time in the typical course. This explains why we all had to study so hard and
make outside office appointments with professors to review critical course
concepts.
The course consists of 36 different thirty-minute lectures,
each of which builds upon the last and is available as a set of DVDs, audio-only
CD packages (our medium of choice), or audio download. Each lecture addresses a
different aspect of the philosophy of science. Lecture titles include the
following:
1) Science
and Philosophy, 2) Popper and the Problem of Demarcation, 3) Further Thoughts
on Demarcation, 4) Einstein, Measurement, and Meaning, 5) Classical Empiricism,
6) Logical Positivism and Verifiability, 7) Logical Positivism, Science, and
Meaning, 8) Holism, 9) Discovery and Justification, 10) Induction as
Illegitimate, 11) Some Solutions and a New Riddle, 12) Instances and
Consequences, 13) Kuhn and the Challenge of History, 14) Revolutions and
Rationality, 15) Assessment of Kuhn, 16) For and Against Method, 17) Sociology, Postmodernism, and Science
Wars, 18) (How) Does Science Explain? 19) Putting the Cause Back in
"Because,” 20) Probability, Pragmatics, and Unification, 21) Laws and
Regularities, 22) Laws and Necessity, 23) Reduction and Progress, 24) Reduction
and Physicalism, 25) New Views of Meaning and Reference, 26) Scientific
Realism, 27) Success, Experience, and Explanation, 28) Realism and Naturalism,
29) Values and Objectivity, 30) Probability, 31) Bayesianism, 32) Problems with
Bayesianism, 33) Entropy and Explanation, 34) Species and Reality, 35) The
Elimination of Persons? and 36) Philosophy and Science.
I included this long list for a quite obvious reason: Simply
looking at the titles of lectures in the course provides quite a bit of
information about what you can expect as you progress through the 18 hours of
philosophical and scientific material.
The first thing that stands out is that the title of the
first and last lectures in the series are very similar, simply transposed. What
you can deduce from this is that philosophy not only influences scientific
practice but the relationship is “give and take” with science having a strong
influence on developments in philosophy as well. Another glance at the titles
will reveal some of the major names involved in the development of a philosophy
of science: Popper, Einstein, and Kuhn. Finally, by looking at the last several
lecture titles we can reasonably predict that probability, and particularly,
Beysian probability figure prominently in the later trends of thinking in
philosophy of science.
We often place an intrinsic faith in science seen in our
acceptance and integration of technology into our daily lives. Yet we also know
that science is sometimes done poorly and its theories proven to be accepted
erroneously. So it’s good to think about science—how it relates to our society,
culture, as well as to us individually. A course in the philosophy of science
attempts to use the tools of philosophy to reflect on these things.
Furthermore, philosophy can be used to evaluate the
assumptions upon which science is based. Should we accept as axiomatic the
assertion that there is a material world and furthermore that we can know, that
is, predict its behavior based on historical observations) anything about
it? Many scientists would obviously
argue that we should and we can, based primarily on the value judgment that
doing so has proven useful—that it’s pragmatic—based on the outcomes of
scientific advancement.
In their recent book The
Grand Design, physicists Stephen Hawking and Leonard Mlodinow (2011) argued
that philosophy of science is dead. Indeed, Dr. Kasser allows that most
of the philosophy of science was done prior to the 20th century and
what remains today is largely semantics. However, a truly curious and skeptical
mind should be cautious about accepting statements like Hawking’s and
Mlodinow’s.
Yes, our materialist perspective has proven very useful in
examining our little corner of the universe, and yes, it is the best
explanation we have now. Yet, failing to keep an open mind about the
possibility that we are wrong (and there is always,
always the possibility that we are wrong) can lead to the kind of dogmatism
in science that has been so vehemently criticized in religion. The first time
this really hit home for me was (no, not when I was watching The Matrix) several years ago when I
happened upon Dr. Nick Bostrom’s (2003) paper, “Are You Living in a Computer
Simulation?”Bostrom’s thesis is presented so clearly in the paper abstract,
there could be no better summary:
This paper argues that at least one
of the following propositions is true: (1) the human species is very likely to
go extinct before reaching a “posthuman” stage; (2) any posthuman civilization
is extremely unlikely to run a significant number of simulations of their
evolutionary history (or variations thereof); (3) we are almost certainly
living in a computer simulation. It follows that the belief that there is a
significant chance that we will one day become posthumans who run
ancestor-simulations is false, unless we are currently living in a simulation.
Note that the definition of posthuman is somewhat
contentious. Bosterom generally refers to posthumanity in terms that it has
developed the capability to exceed material and energy constraints due to
technology. While this topic is a slight digression from the main focus at
hand, the point I wish to make I that philosophy still has plenty to say about
science and technology and their applications.
“Philosophers &
Philosophy in Science”
Chances are, if you’ve ever had a course or series of
courses in research methods, you will have had at least some exposure to our
first prominent philosopher of science: Karl Popper. (Please resist the urge to
call him John Popper, the singer/songwriter and supernatural harmonica player
for Blues Traveller. Karl Popper was a teacher at the London
School of Economics and he was originally from the lively intellectual city of Vienna. Popper’s unique
insight was the concept of falsifiability. Inductive reasoning presented a
difficulty in that no matter how many confirmatory observations a scientist
makes, he or she can never prove something to be universally true, such as all
ravens are black. However, according to Popper our hypothesis can be falsified.
One observation of a white raven falsifies the hypothesis: All ravens are black.
This was also Popper’s answer to the demarcation
problem—we’re doing science if and only if our hypotheses are falsifiable. This
helps us to further distance genuine scientific inquiry from pseudoscience.
Unfortunately finding this distinction continues to be a problem for those in
the general public—such as people who buy “magnetic energy bracelets.”
In the concluding post, Philosophy of Science II, I will
look at the following topics and how they relate to our basis of the philosophy
of science: Einstein, Classical Empiricism, Logical Positivism (such as A. J.
Ayer’s), Holism, Hume and Induction, Kuhn’s historical perspective, sociology
of science, postmodernism, laws, reduction and physicalism, scientific realism,
probability, Bayesianism, and entropy.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Comments, criticisms, or corrections? Let me know what you think!